10
THE FIRST-BEST THEORY
OF TAXATION
PUBLIC CHOICE AND PARETO-OPTIMAL REDISTRIBUTION
Pareto-Optimality and the Overall Distribution of Income
Pareto-Optimal Redistribution and the Poor
What Motivates Charity: Should Aid Be In-Kind or Cash?
Are Pareto-Optimal Redistributions Enough?
ALTRUISM, FREE RIDING, AND CROWDING OUT OF
PRIVATE CHARITY
Do People Free Ride?
Does Public Assistance Crowd Out Private Giving?
OTHER MOTIVATIONS FOR REDISTRIBUTIVE TRANSFERS
Public Insurance
Social Status
Equal Access
Having covered the mainstream normative theory of public expenditures
in Chapters 2 through 9, the mainstream Wrst-best theory of taxation is easy
to describe. We saw that Wrst-best public expenditure theory addresses two
fundamental questions:
1. In what area of economic activity can the government legitimately
became involved?
2. What decision rules should the government follow in each area?
In answering these questions, public expenditure theory provides both a
complete prescription for government expenditures and a complete norma-
tive theory of taxation. There is no Wrst-best theory of taxation distinct from
the Wrst-best theory of public expenditures. All we need do is review the main
results from the previous chapters.
The Wrst point to recall is that taxes can only enhance social welfare in a
Wrst-best environment. They are not at all the necessary evil that the public
sometimes makes them out to be. To the contrary, Wrst-best taxes promote
307
the public interest in eYciency and equity as they support society's quest for a
social welfare maximum at the bliss point. They have no other purpose in the
mainstream Wrst-best theory.
Regarding eYciency, either public expenditure theory describes some
particular tax necessary to achieve a pareto-optimal allocation of resources
or it does not. If not, then taxes have no further role to play in promoting
economic eYciency. For example, we found that exclusive goods that gener-
ate either consumption or production externalities can be allocated correctly
with a set of Pigovian taxes (subsidies) equal to the aggregate marginal
damage (beneWt) resulting from the externality. Similarly, decreasing cost
services require marginal-cost pricing for pareto optimality. Whether one
refers to these publicly set prices as admission ``fees,'', highway and bridge
``tolls,'' or transit ``fares'' hardly matters. The marginal cost charges for these
services can always be thought of as taxes set according to the competitive
interpretation of the beneWts-received principle of taxation, the only inter-
pretation consistent with economic eYciency.
One can analyze the eYciency costs of distorting taxation, of course. In
fact, the analysis of distorting taxation dates from the very beginnings of
modern public Wnance when taxes received far more attention than expend-
itures. But distorting taxation is inherently part of second-best theory.
At times Wrst-best public expenditure theory requires certain government
expenditures without specifying exactly how to collect the revenues to Wnance
these expenditures. Leading examples are Samuelsonian nonexclusive public
goods and subsidies to cover the deWcits of decreasing cost services when
prices (taxes) are set equal to marginal costs. The only eYciency criterion in
these instances is that the taxes be lump sum to avoid generating distortions
that would prevent the Wrst-best pareto-optimal conditions from holding.
Any pattern of lump-sum taxation preserves the eYcient allocation of these
goods.
As we have also seen, Wrst-best theory solves the problem of how to
collect the lump-sum taxes to Wnance these expenditures. The required taxes
(transfers) simply become part of the pattern of lump-sum taxes and transfers
that satisfy the interpersonal equity conditions of social welfare maximiza-
tion of the form
qW
q U
h
qU
h
qI
h
all h 1, ...,H
where I
h
can loosely be thought of as lump-sum income.
1
Whether the
requirement of equalizing the social marginal utilities of income is viewed
as part of Wrst-best expenditure theory or Wrst-best tax theory is a matter of
semantics. Either way, the interpersonal equity conditions are the only equity
1
More precisely, it is a good or factor (presumably the numeraire) singled out for taxation
and transfer.
308 THE FIRST-BEST THEORY OF TAXATION

Get Public Finance, 2nd Edition now with the O’Reilly learning platform.

O’Reilly members experience books, live events, courses curated by job role, and more from O’Reilly and nearly 200 top publishers.