P
H
h1
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
ik
P
H
h1
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
i1
F
k
F
1
all i 1, ...,H (6:9)
any k 2, ...,N
The right-hand side of (6.9) has a standard interpretation, the marginal rate
of transformation (MRT) in production between goods (factors) k and 1. The
left-hand side has no standard interpretation, however. As written, it is a
ratio of marginal impacts on social welfare from consuming (supplying) the
two goods (factors), and there is no way to simplify the expression. In
particular, the social welfare terms, qW/qU
h
, do not cancel, so that the rule
is not really a pareto-optimal or eY ciency condition at all. Recall that pareto-
optimal conditions do not contain social welfare terms. In this worst of all
worlds, then, the model does not dichotomize into interpersonal equity and
pareto-optimal conditions, the only exception we will encounter in all of Part
II. All the decision rules are of the interpersonal equity type and can be
achieved only by lump-sum redistributions of all goods and factors, a truly
hopeless situation. Moreover, the competitive market system, which equates
marginal rates of substitution in consumption to marginal rates of transform-
ation, would be absolutely useless. Nothing short of a complete government
takeover of the economy would be capable of satisfying the Wrst-order
conditions for social welfare maximization, even in principle.
THE EXISTENCE OF AT LEAST ONE PURE PRIVATE GOOD
Fortunately, the real world is not so riddled with consumption externalities.
A large number of goods are pure private goods, or close enough to pure
private goods that a government would not consider intervening in their
markets. To keep the discussion as general as possible, however, let us assume
that there is only one pure private good in the economy, the Wrst. Formally,
qU
h
/qX
i1
0, i 6 h. The other (N 1) goods and factors remain pure public
goods. As it turns out, only one private good is needed to resurrect the
dichotomy between the pareto-optimal and interpersonal equity conditions
that normally exists in Wrst-best analysis and to retain a role for the competi-
tive market system in allocating all the goods and factors.
With a single private good, the social welfare maximization problem
becomes:
max
X
ik
; X
h1
WU
h
X
ik
;X
h1
s:t: F
P
H
i1
X
ik
;
P
H
h1
X
h1
0
6. CONSUMPTION EXTERNALITIES 159
where k 2, ..., N. Good 1 has been written separately to indicate speciW-
cally that it is a pure private good.
Interpersonal Equity Conditions
Consider the interpersonal equity conditions with respect to good 1, the pure
private good. The Wrst-order conditions are
3
X
h1
:
qW
qU
h
qU
h
X
h1
lF
1
(6:10)
X
i1
:
qW
qU
i
qU
i
X
i1
lF
1
(6:11)
or
qW
qU
h
qU
h
X
h1
lF
1
all h 1, ...,H (6:12)
Equation (6.12) is identical to the interpersonal equity conditions in the
standard model of Chapter 2. Assume the government can redistribute X
1
lump sum to achieve this condition as part of its Wrst-best policy strategy.
Pareto-Optimal Conditions
As above, consider the Wrst-order conditions with respect to two goods
(factors) consumed (supplied) by any one person i, say X
ik
and X
i1
. The
choice of k is arbitrary, but good 1, the private good, must be one of the two
goods chosen. The Wrst-order conditions are
X
ik
:
P
H
h1
qW
qU
h
qU
h
X
ik
lF
k
(6:13)
X
i1
:
qW
qU
i
qU
i
qX
i1
lF
1
(6:14)
Dividing Eq. (6.13) by (6.14) yields:
P
H
h1
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
ik
qW
qU
i
qU
i
qX
i1
F
k
F
1
, for k 2, ...,N (6:15)
Condition (6.15) can be simpliWed if the government has satisWed the
interpersonal equity conditions for good 1. The left-hand side is a summation
3
l is the Lagrangian multiplier associated with F ( ).
160 THE EXISTENCE OF AT LEAST ONE PURE PRIVATE GOOD
of social welfare terms over a common denominator,
qW
qU
i
qU
i
qX
i1
. But, if inter-
personal equity holds,
qW
qU
i
qU
i
X
i1
lF
1
all i 1, ...,H (6:16)
Selectively substitute for the denominator term by term, matching up the
social welfare terms, and write:
qW
qU
1
qU
1
qX
ik
qW
qU
1
qU
1
qX
11
, ...,
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
ik
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
h1
, ...,
qW
qU
H
qU
H
qX
ik
qW
qU
H
qU
H
qX
H1
F
k
F
1
,(6:17)
any k 2, ...,N
P
H
h1
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
ik
qW
qU
h
qU
h
qX
h1
2
6
6
6
4
3
7
7
7
5
F
k
F
1
all i 1, ...,H
any k 2, ...,N
(6:18)
The social welfare indexes, qW/qU
h
cancel term by term, yielding:
P
H
h1
qU
h
qX
ik
qU
h
qX
h1
2
6
6
6
4
3
7
7
7
5
F
k
F
1
(6:19)
The left-hand side of Eq. (6.19) has a standard pareto-optimal interpretation,
devoid of social welfare terms. It is a sum of marginal rates of substitution,
each person's marginal rate of substitution (MRS) between person i's con-
sumption of good k and her own consumption of the pure private good.
Thus, the rule can be written as:
P
H
h1
MRS
h
X
ik
; X
h1
MRT
k; 1
for all i 1, ...,H
any k 2, ...,N
(6:20)
Note carefully that the ability to cancel the social welfare terms is not just
a formal ``trick.'' It implies an optimal Wrst-best policy action, a lump sum
redistribution that satisWes the interpersonal equity conditions for good
(factor) 1. Without the optimal redistribution, the terms would not cancel
and all the policy implications of the pareto-optimal conditions which we are
about to discuss become irrelevant. Conditions (6.19) would not be the
necessary conditions for a social welfare maximum. We will employ this
6. CONSUMPTION EXTERNALITIES 161
Get Public Finance, 2nd Edition now with the O’Reilly learning platform.
O’Reilly members experience books, live events, courses curated by job role, and more from O’Reilly and nearly 200 top publishers.